How much should you plan to spend each year
in retirement? That depends in large part on your budget. How much will it cost
to satisfy basic needs and what other sorts of discretionary expenses do you
have in mind? It also depends on the resources you have available, such as your
financial assets, Social Security and other pensions, and other possibilities
such as part-time work. For assets which do not provide guaranteed lifetime
incomes, there is a tradeoff at work that spending more now risks the
possibility for having to cut back on spending later in life. We may need to
sacrifice some of the more discretionary types of expenses now in order to save
enough to meet basic needs when financial markets are not cooperating. How do
we balance this tradeoff?
The answer provided by economists is that
we should seek to maximize our overall lifetime satisfaction subject to the
constraints we face in terms of our available resources. To know how to
maximize this satisfaction, we need to think not simply in terms of spending
amounts, but rather how much value is provided by that spending.
Economists call this ‘utility
maximization.’ Lots of people will have horrible flashbacks to their principles
of economics class and shudder at the thought of this term. They will want to
avoid discussing it. They will say that to know how to maximize utility, we
need to know the shape of the utility function and the appropriate ‘risk
aversion coefficient.’ They will say that this is essentially impossible. They
will say it is nonsense dreamed up by ivory tower types.
While there some truth to all of that, the
reality is that it is impossible to
avoid utility maximization. It is just that with other analytical tools, we
may end up maximizing a utility function which doesn’t make much sense. Utility
is really about assigning a value for the enjoyment providing by your spending,
and even if you think you are avoiding utility, you really are not.
Consider the traditional failure rate
measure for safe withdrawal rate studies. It is the probability that financial
assets are depleted during one’s lifetime or during a specified time period
such as 30 years. The idea of safe withdrawal rate studies is to choose a
spending strategy that keeps the probability of failure at a sufficiently low
level. Whether you like it or not, this is a utility function. It defines the
value of additional spending as basically zero. There is no benefit from
spending more, it can only hurt. Importance is only placed on the outcomes
where wealth is depleted. And so, spending is pushed downward to avoid this. It
is a utility function which only focuses on downside risks and not on any of the positives of spending more.
What is a measure that considers both
downside risk and upside positives? A simple one could be either total lifetime
spending or average lifetime spending. Now there is benefit from spending more…
it helps to push up the average. At the same time though, the tradeoff between
spending more now and spending less later also appears, because later spending
reductions would reduce the total and average. You increase spending if it
provides a net gain after accounting for this.
You may think ‘average lifetime spending’ is
not a utility function, but it is. And
it is a rather odd one, because it assumes that the value of additional
spending is the same no matter how much you spend. The enjoyment you get from
eating the 1st slice of pizza matches the enjoyment you get from
eating the 10th slice of pizza. This seems to fly in the face of
human experience.
The reason that the economist’s conception
of utility maximization seems frightening is that it says the value of
additional spending is not simply linear in this way, but it rather has a curved
shape. Curves must be defined with more complicated mathematical equations than
lines.
With the curve, more spending is better
than less, but the additional value provided by more and more spending
diminishes as spending increases. The highest priority expenses provide great
value since they fulfill essential human needs such as food and shelter. But as
expenses increase higher and higher, well there are just so many nights you can
spend in 5-star hotels before starting to get fed up with the experience. The
additional life-improving value provided by spending will surely be less as
spending grows.
I illustrate this idea in the following
figure. It shows the value of spending for two different utility functions. The
curved utility function (for the technically inclined, it is the logarithm of
spending) shows the properties that spending more always provides greater
value, but the increases in value are diminishing as spending increases. Looking
toward spending reductions, the impact of such reductions grows dramatically
larger as spending falls lower and lower.
We can quibble about what the exact shape
of this curve should be to properly define the value of spending. In this case,
the increased value in moving from 0.1 to 1 matches the increased value in
moving from 1 to 10. Is that realistic? Well, it is probably hard to say even
for someone carefully studying their budget and trying to assign value to
different expenses.
But this brings us back to my earlier
point. It is impossible to avoid using a utility function. In a lot of cases,
the value assigned to spending implicit in the outcome measure may not really make
much sense when you think about it. Though the blue curve in my figure may not
be a precise match for anyone’s utility, I think it comes a lot closer to being
correct than the green line (implied by average spending) or than a measure like
failure rates which only looks at downside and ignores upside.
I’d be happy with just using the relatively
simple blue curve in that figure. I think it gets us a lot closer to something
realistic. We add up the values provided by each year’s spending amount over
the lifetime. If we wish, multiplying later spending amounts by the probability of surviving to that age is also a possibility that will give more importance
to what happens in the early part of retirement. But this is optional and
depends on your own personal preferences.
What are the implications of defining the
value of spending in this way? It does put importance both on downside risk and
on the value of more spending. It provides a way to determine the proper balance.
Spending more is nice and it provides more value. At the same time, that
increase in value may not be enough to counteract the potential reduced
spending that may have to happen later on. Another implication is that
consumption smoothing (spending the same amount each year) is optimal, which is
why economists tend to like real fixed income annuities (SPIAs). Without
annuities, it is hard to achieve smooth consumption when spending down from a
portfolio of volatile assets. Variable withdrawal strategies which respond to
market performance tend to outperform the traditional ‘constant
inflation-adjusted withdrawal amount until wealth is gone’ strategy. But
something called ‘habit formation’ can also be introduced to the utility
function which penalizes reductions to spending on account that people don’t
like reducing their standard of living. This will help smooth spending patterns.
And so with this tool we have a more
realistic way to compare retirement income strategies that provide the best
balance of spending over the lifetime.
Wade –
ReplyDeleteMajor thanks for describing the concept and its value so well. And special thanks for addressing the horror of that word, "utility"
The concept as you describe it is indeed valuable. But for people who understand the shamefully unethical way the high priests of investment theory and “education” have MIS-used the utility concept in conjunction with modern portfolio theory, the word utility is POISON.
What they have done is divert the investor from pursuit of her investment’s utility, which of course is purchasing power for her needs and goals. They avoid addressing what might best for her utility, cut off the analysis short of that. Instead they pretend to determine her tradeoff preferences between a pair of techie measures that most investors don’t understand – return-rate arithmetic mean and return-rate standard deviation. To lubricate this deception, they label return-rate arithmetic mean “expected return,” although they know full well that return is not expected, and label return-rate standard deviation “risk” to divert the investor’s focus to her short-term fears.
Of course, the investor cannot see how her choice of tradeoff between these techie one-year measures affects her utility, probabilities for purchasing power for her future needs and goals. That would require mathematical application of the probabilities reflected by those techie measures to the dollars and years of her cash flow plan and future needs and goals, applying compounding along the way.
But what the heck, they say. We may be violating our responsibility to the investor, dooming her to sunset years in poverty. But we tenured academicians will have what we need for mathematical fun and games in the professors’ playground up in the ivory tower.
I hope that in your valuable work, when you use the concept you will say “value” instead of that word those academicians have poisoned.
Dick Purcell
Thanks Dick.
DeleteI was trying to emphasize, as has been expressed by Joe Tomlinson, that it is important to translate spending amounts into something that better represents the value provided by that spending.
Yes, Wade, I appreciate and admire what you and Joe Tomlinson are doing – explaining the concept to folks to help them think out their priorities.
DeleteMy purpose was/is to help SUPPORT what you each/both are doing, by separating it from the disgrace associated with the word “utility.” Shamefully, many economists use that word and MIS-use the concept through absurdly inadequate methods of leaping from Granny the victim to an alleged mathematical representation of her priorities. The effect is to throw Granny under the bus in order to create mathematical sport and technical publications for said economists.
Dick Purcell